[JPS logo]

The Genetic Epistemologist

The Journal of the Jean Piaget Society

Volume 25, Number 2 (Spring 1997)

Genetic Epistemologist Homepage

Table of Contents:

  1. Inhelder’s Valedictory (Terrance Brown)

  2. Announcement of 15th Advanced Course, Archives Piaget

  3. An Interpretation of Operational Thought as Internalised Transformations (Andre Hopper)

  4. Minutes of the Annual Business Meeting

  5. Minutes of the June Board of Directors Meeting

  6. Editor’s Note (Chris Lalonde)


Inhelder’s Valedictory

by Terrance Brown

In planning this memorial edition of the GE, Chris Lalonde, its editor, asked me, Edith Ackermann, and Michel Ferrari to provide excerpts from the translation of Le Cheminement des Découvertes de l’Enfant (Inhelder & Cellérier, 1992), Bärbel Inhelder’s last book. The publisher of the English edition, Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, has graciously granted us permission to do so. In order for me to orient you quickly, let me first offer some brief remarks that I recently put together for a memorial issue of Human Development.

As far as Inhelder’s contributions are concerned, there is no doubt that Le Cheminement des Découvertes de l’Enfant constitutes a valedictory. Like all farewells, it attempts to make sense of a certain piece of history. In the present case, the history at issue is not just a chronicle of the Genevan School in which she was so intimately involved. Nor is it only an exposition of how the structure-function bifurcation developed into the beginnings of a reconciliation between epistemological and psychological approaches. If one is willing to read between the lines, it also tells the story of how Inhelder, as a person, sought to distinguish herself from Piaget and develop her own identity as a scientist.

Although it is almost certain that Bärbel would not have been comfortable with the parallels I am about to draw, it is my conviction that, taken in concert with her Autobiography (Inhelder, 1989), her chapters in Le Cheminement are in many ways analogous to Brünhilde’s "Immolation." In her great valedictory, Brünhilde recounts the story of a hero, ponders his faults and virtues, evaluates his successes and his failures, and in the end establishes her own identity through an act that accomplishes both her father’s and the hero’s goal: the reestablishment of the proper relation between love and power. To my mind, Inhelder’s case is similar. In her Autobiography and in Le Cheminement, Inhelder who, like Brünhilde, gave up her godhead–her place in Valhalla–in order to defend a great figure and his ideals came in the end to reclaim her heritage, psychology, through an act announcing a new world order: the reconciliation of Piagetian epistemology with cognitive psychology . . . Although it seems likely that she suspected for many years (if not from the very beginning) that Piaget’s epistemic subject was not what psychology was all about, she did not say so until the very end. Only after decades of studying how universal categories and rational knowledge are constructed did she voice her doubts. What she concluded was that epistemology, by itself, could not explain discovery and that cognitive psychology, by itself, could not explain rationality. She sought, therefore, to find what Piaget would have called a tertium quid (an intermediate term), but not by restoring epistemology to philosophy as Brünhilde restored the Rhinegold to the Rhine. Her tack was, rather, to suggest a world in which the gods of Genevan epistemology and the gnomes of American cognitivism would, through some sort of licit union, give rise to a psychology that had the universal traits of Piaget’s epistemic subjects and the individual traits of real people with real histories living real lives. That, essentially, is what the work on strategies and procedures was all about. (Brown, submitted).

That said, I think it will be evident why I have selected the following sections from Chapter 1 and the Final Remarks. The title of that chapter is "Toward a Psychological Constructivism: Structures? Procedures?–Two Indissociables"; the excerpt chosen is subtitled "What Subject for Psychology?"

 

WHAT SUBJECT FOR PSYCHOLOGY?

by Bärbel Inhelder and Denys de Caprona

It is possible to distinguish the way a problem is understood in terms of the child’s general interpretation of reality from the means and the specific knowledge the child uses to solve it. The interpretation of reality derives from the child’s natural epistemology. That epistemology engenders "world views" focused either on understanding the world or on understanding oneself as a thinking subject. For example, young children have world views about why clouds move (Piaget, 1927) as well as world views about where words and thoughts are located (Piaget, 1926). When there is a particular problem to be solved, however, a world view is not enough. In such instances, the knowledge brought into play is essentially specific, and the way it is used is highly individual. This difference constitutes a significant dividing line within genetic psychology.

We began our research in the strong belief that genetic psychology had, up to that point, provided a remarkable description of people’s spontaneous epistemology and of the structures that organize their knowledge. It had sketched out a general architecture of knowledge in terms of a given epistemic subject’s structures. At the same time, we were convinced that it had not really analyzed individual know-how and that this left a vast field of conduct to be studied. Individual know-how involves a variety of cognitive schemes that are more heuristic than general knowledge structures are.

Piaget used the term "epistemic subject" to emphasize the focus of his studies and to mark the reflected and formal nature of structures. He defined the epistemic subject as the nucleus common to every individual’s knowledge at a given developmental level. He conceived subjects, therefore, in terms of their nomothetic rather than their idiosyncratic characteristics. This has led to important misunderstandings that make it essential to distinguish between the epistemic and the psychological subject. Certain psychologists have reproached Piaget and his school for studying a "disembodied" subject devoid of life, but this misses the deep and enduring meaning of Piaget’s approach. Because of Piaget, the epistemic subject is no longer the subject of philosophical knowledge. Rather, it is the subject of rational knowledge, of scientific knowledge broadly construed to include the rationality of intuition or common-sense (just as one speaks of formal and intuitive geometry).

One of the most original aspects of Piaget’s work is that it was centered on basic categories of knowledge without which there can be no adaptation to reality and no coherent thought. Piaget created the foundations of a psychology dealing with the construction of constitutive notions like space, time, causality, etc. That is why the epistemic subject becomes the subject of normative knowledge. Any psychology that would study the epistemic subject must deal with norms and, in doing so, must use models drawn from scientific thought. What interests us about all of this is how the epistemic subject’s normative framework functions, how it allows the psychological subject to grasp reality and organize his activities. Individual conduct can only unfold within the limits of the connections inherent within the categories of the cognitive system. In order to study individual psychological subjects, therefore, focus must be shifted to a different set of categories dealing with these connections (Inhelder, Ackermann-Valladão, Blanchet, Karmiloff-Smith, Kilcher-Hagedorn, Montangero, & Robert, 1976; Inhelder & Piaget, 1979). The observer must try to uncover the dynamics of subject’s cognitive behavior: their goals, the means they choose, how they monitor the results of their actions and estimate progress toward their goal, and the specific heuristics they use to reach goals that may be attained by several different paths. The aim of all of this is to unlock the secrets of the subject’s psychological functioning and to tease out the general characteristics of his procedures. In other words, it is to discern the organization and finality of his action sequences.

Does this mean that these two types of subjects, epistemic and psychological, require completely different psychological approaches? We believe that the distinction between them is by no means absolute. In general, functional psychologies try to preserve the subject as a whole by taking into account everything that might help elucidate cognitive functioning. They cannot, of course, ever do this completely, since they can only study what is accessible at a given moment. Admitting and accepting this limitation, we nevertheless attempt to consider the knowing subject in global and comprehensive fashion. At the same time, the differences in questions and methods, so striking when one moves from structural to functional analysis, should not conceal the fact that it is always the knowing subject in his totality who is being studied. The heuristic distinction between epistemic subject and psychological subject merely reflects complementary ways in which researchers elaborate what the subject knows. In the first case, the emphasis is on normative knowledge; in the second case, it is on pragmatic and empirical knowledge.

To avoid misunderstanding, we need a shared approach to and a common conception of the knowing subject. Within such an approach, categorical analysis of the epistemic subject and functional analysis of the psychological subject must both be accepted as legitimate and complementary. The idea of a subject, active and constructive, engaged in knowing not only the world but also itself must be acknowledged. Such a conception cannot, of course, just be decreed a presupposition for all research; it has to be spelled out and justified. When that is done, it provides a rich ground for research centered on the psychological subject, while at the same time fully recognizing the existence of epistemic functioning.

Once the necessary conjuncture of the two approaches was accepted, we had to figure out what the specific features of the functional perspective were. We realized early on that teleonomy and axiology have a great deal to do with how knowledge becomes individualized. The psychological subject interested us as a knowing subjects, but one with intentions and values. This led us to put special emphasis on the teleonomic and axiological aspects of cognitive activity and to study subjects from the point of view of the goals they set themselves and the values they attributed to things.

The differences between the epistemic subject’s structures and the psychological subject’s functioning arise from the fact that "structure . . . was (and remains) for Piaget an instrument that is both efficient and adequate for characterizing epistemologically what is `universal’ in various subjects’ knowledge, but not for characterizing the individual functioning of the knowing subject’s mind" (Cellérier, 1987). In other words, Piaget’s search for "universals" was an index of his interest in the norms of what he called "the society of minds," a community based on a cooperative exchange of ideas. There can be no doubt that genetic epistemology has helped us understand how existing knowledge has been constructed, but it does not tell the whole story. We wanted to go a bit further and look at subjects as they used and constructed their knowledge something along the lines of Boesch (1991, p. 366) who, in the context of contemporary cultural psychology, has developed a theory of action in which "human-beings interact with their environment in a dynamic way, thereby structuring the object and its social world, as well as the self and its action- potentialities."

This new orientation implies that interest, a cognitive conduct central to functional studies, is no longer (or not always) the same as what passes for interest in studies of the epistemic subject. In fact, the conduct focused on in the studies reported here lies outside the epistemological and psychological fields chosen by Piaget. We no longer study the construction of the great concepts underlying knowledge of reality nor do we describe the structural organization specific to each epistemic domain. Rather, we attempt to shed light on the procedures elaborated in ordinary practical contexts. To that end, we ask ourselves, "How does the child make sense of the task? How does he select and specify the cognitive tools he will use? Are there different representations of each situation and does their adequacy vary? How does the child monitor and evaluate his progress?"

 

And in the Final Remarks of the book, Inhelder (along with Guy Cellérier, Denys de Caprona, and Jean-Jacques Ducret) concludes:

"Our goal . . . was to found a "psychological constructivism" by focusing attention not on the [structural aspects of the] epistemic subject but on the functional processes of the "psychological subject" confronted with particular tasks . . . From our perspective, three problems appear essential: the nature of the complex relations between the procedural study of knowledge in children and artificial intelligence, the relations between microgenesis and macrogenesis, and finally the question of the role of cognitive schemes in psychological functioning.

In so far as the first problem is concerned, by rehabilitating the notion of finality, cybernetics, as well as–in a small way and perhaps without knowing it–artificial intelligence have made us put not just action but even more the teleonomic dimension of action at the center of such functioning . . . However, our reference to the modes of teleonomic and procedural analysis belonging to these two disciplines should not be taken to mean that we have fallen into the trap of trying to reduce psychological phenomena to a caricatural form of information processing, a reductionism too often present in the thought of contemporary cognitivists . . . As for microgenesis and macrogenesis, it is a matter of processes which play out on different time scales. Following the sequential playing out of procedures as closely as possible, does not simply put the steps and transitions of macrogenesis under a magnifying glass (as we did in our studies on operatory learning). The function of the two forms of cognitive elaboration is different, just as are the methods by which they can be demonstrated . . . The study of macrogenesis centers on the steps by which the general categories of knowledge are constructed, [while] microgenetic study concerns itself with the multitude of procedures invented by the child and with the way in which the child modifies procedures and puts them to the test . . . Nevertheless, our investigations do suggest interdependencies. If macrogenesis provides a set of possibilities and a norm of accommodation for each developmental level, the microgenetic counterpart of this is that procedures contribute to macrogenesis . . . the interface between macrogenesis and microgenesis being provided by schemes in so far as schemes include a procedural as well as a structural dimension. Schemes, above all else, are coodinators of action . . . the attribute of microgenetic studies is to bear on finalized conduct, and an original result of our studies has been to show how the teleonomic and causal aspects of conduct are coordinated . . . Would it, then, be too audacious to suggest that a constructivist cognitivism [of the sort ought outlined here] ought both to orient future thought and research on the construction of machines with psychogenetic architecture and to provide always deeper insights into the processes of guidance, regulation, and evaluation that underlie children’s journeys to discovery?"

 

References

Boesch, E. E. (1991). Symbolic Addict Theory and Cultural Psychology. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.

Brown, T. (Submitted). Bärbel Inhelder and the Fall of Valhalla. Human Development.

Cellérier, G. (1987). La psychologie génétique et le cognitivisme. Le débat, 47, 116-129.

Inhelder, B. (1989). Bärbel Inhelder (Autobiography). In G. Lindzey (Ed), A History of Psychology in Autobiography. Stanford: Stanford University Press (pp. 208-243).

Inhelder, B., Ackermann-Valladão, E., Blanchet, A., Karmiloff-Smith, A., Kilcher-Hagedorn, H., Montangero, J. & Robert, M. (1976). Des Structures Cognitives aux Procédures de Découverte: Esquisse de Recherches en Cours. Archives de psychologie, 44 (171), 57- 72.

Inhelder, B., & Cellérier, G. (1992). Le Cheminement des Découvertes de l’Enfant. Neuchâtel: Delachaux & Niestlé. (To appear in English as Children’s Journey’s Discovery, T. Brown, E. Ackermann, and M. Ferrari (Eds). Malwah NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.)

Piaget. J. (1927). La causalité physique chez l’enfant. Paris: Alcan.

Piaget, J. (1926). La représentation du monde chez l’enfant. Paris: Alcan.

Table of Contents


Working with Piaget. In memoriam Bärbel Inhelder

15th advanced course of the Archives Jean Piaget

University of Geneva, September 21-24, 1998

The name of Bärbel Inhelder is generally associated with Jean Piaget, the founder of genetic epistemology. For about 40 years, Bärbel Inhelder collaborated with the "patron" providing him with an important part of the experimental data on which he built his theory. However, her specific and determinant contribution to the development of Piagetian theory has not yet received the credit it deserves. Very few people know, for instance, that she was at the origin of the discovery of the stage of formal operations.

Her attachment and admiration for Piaget led her to create, in 1974, the Fondation Archives Jean Piaget, a research center whose aim is to study Piagetian theory. It is within this framework that Bärbel Inhelder organized, for many years, a series of advanced courses for researchers and advanced students. Thus it is natural that, one year after her death, the Archives Jean Piaget have decided to honor her in their next course entitled: Working with Piaget. In memoriam. Bärbel Inhelder. This course aims at bringing to the fore Bärbel Inhelder’s works, not only the ones she co-authored with Piaget, but also all those, that were personal and have partly remained unknown. Following the chronological order of these works, the advanced course will deal with various topics such as conservation, mental handicap, perspective taking, formal thought, longitudinal and intercultural research, learning of cognitive structures and strategies in problem solving. Each topic will be addressed by a researcher of international renown, who will highlight Bärbel Inhelder’s contribution, as well as the actual state of the domain. In addition, 4 workshops developing the different presentations of the conference will give the opportunity to the participants to discuss and exchange actively their ideas. Finally, an afternoon will be devoted to poster presentations.

For more information, contact:

Archives Jean Piaget
18, route des Acacias
1227 Acacias-Genève
Switzerland
tel.: + 41 22 705 70 21
FAX: + 41 22 300 20 46
e-mail: tryphon@uni2a.unige.ch

Table of Contents


An Interpretation of Operational Thought as Internalised Transformations

by Andre Hopper

Introduction

Piaget’s descriptions and definitions of operational thought were based upon the idea of an operation conceived as an internalised action where the latter appears little different to that of a physical and motor movement of a limb, albeit internal to the mind and immediately reversible and mobile. This essay is an attempt to enhance and "correct" the conception of operations in the hope that our understanding will benefit if we redefine the operation as an internalised transformation that constitutes an already-abstracted attribute. The analysis attempts to resolve some apparent paradoxes presented by Piaget’s descriptions of concrete operations, and also to reject Seltman & Seltman’s (1985) main criticism of his work.

Operations as Actions

Piaget repeatedly defined operations as internalised actions, and often went so far as to say they derive directly from the subject’s physical actions as enacted in sensorimotor behaviour. The emphasis upon physical action created a terminology that is perhaps more metaphorical than exact when it comes to describing the activity of operational thought. For example, with the operation defined as an "action" enacted in thought, the grouping structure of operations (where each operation is always implicitly bound up with a whole system or structure of inter-related operations), together with the emphasis upon the operation as a reversible action, leads one to imagine the mind as comprising a system of extremely rapid and "machine-like" executions of these actions quite literally. However, this kind of terminology should be treated more as a metaphor or analogy, which, as such, leads to its own problems.

Piaget’s treatment of concrete operations, as actions, also leads to the problem of defining the qualitative difference between the two types of reversibility. On the one hand, we have operations where the reversibility is characterised by direct negation: for example, the action to place an object is negated by the action to remove the object. And on the other hand, we have operations where the reversibility is characterised by reciprocity: the relation of "bigger than" is not put in opposition to the relation of "not bigger than", but to the relation of "smaller than". However, this last statement in itself shows us the difficulty of realising operations of reciprocity as deriving from physical actions enacted by the subject: what is the action of "bigger than"? Rather, the relation of "bigger than" is just that–a relation–and not necessarily the direct result of a physical action.

If Piaget’s apparent reduction of operations to physical actions is difficult to sustain, it would be wrong to conclude that he did indeed reduce operations to actions. In fact, one can argue that Piaget made a number of attempts to provide different qualitative descriptions of operational thought. In "The Origin of Intelligence in the Child" (Piaget, 1985) , in the table in the introduction, we see the function of assimilation, not accommodation, as leading to the operations. For another, in "Possibility and Necessity", Piaget (1987) elaborated upon the functions of differentiation and integration as the mechanism for abstracting from the concrete to the abstract. And, in the various essays on equilibration, Piaget attempted to describe operational structures not so much in terms of systems of actions, but rather as systems of dynamic equilibrium. Of course, all these different perspectives amount to the same thing, not to a change of view. Piaget was attempting to describe better and better what he saw as the (rather difficult) truth, and was not simply changing his mind.

Moreover, with the difficulty of maintaining Piaget’s apparent reduction of operations to physical actions, it would be wrong to go to the other extreme of relying only upon notions of passive perceptions of physical relations. Perception, when conceived as the rather inert function of mere assimilation, does not sufficiently allow for the fact that cognitive structures develop. More significantly, preoperational and operational structures do not just change, but undergo profound qualitative advances in their capabilities. To get from one level to the next, the subject has to be active within the milieu of those relations, the internalisation of which precisely defines the next level over the previous. The definition of an operation as an action retains the sense of active and constructive participation by the subject, whereas some notion of simply "seeing" (i.e. perceiving) these relations fails to address these necessary attributes.

So, concluding with the claim that to define operations as internalised actions leads to difficulties we could do without (and more such examples will be described below), we now have to suggest a more useful terminology that does not suffer the deficiencies Piaget’s own terminology sought to overcome. In what follows, we introduce terms which do not change in any way the logic of Piaget’s description of operations–they only change (and hopefully assist) in our understanding of them.

Sensorimotor and Intuitive Objects

The subject, as a centre of activity, stands in opposition to the object, which, initially (and practically), is external to the subject. Through the functions of assimilation and accommodation, and through the differentiation and integration of the subject’s structures; through the reciprocal adaptation of structures producing greater and greater abstractions; the subject eventually comes to abstract all the defining properties and determinants of that object. This process of abstraction results, on the one hand, in the subject’s internalisation of that object, and on the other hand, in the subject’s ability to produce that object. For example, in the case of sensorimotor development, the sensorimotor object is one upon which the infant physically acts; and at the culmination of sensorimotor development, the subject has internalised the object to the extent that objects can now be mentally produced as representations.

Within the perspective of a qualitative development, there is, then, a unique relationship between the subject and the object. But the real usefulness of this description is in the identification of the object as such. When sensorimotor development concludes, there is the two-fold conquest of both the internalisation and produce-ability of the (sensorimotor) object. What this means is that the subject’s intelligence conserves the object (at that qualitative level of activity–i.e. physical) despite whatever transformations are imposed upon the object. Alternatively, we can say that the object gains permanence from the subject’s point of view; and yet another way of saying the same thing is to state that the subject’s intelligence compensates for disturbances and perturbances imposed upon (or perceived from) the object. With this terminology, we are then introducing a model whereby the subject becomes able to produce a mental model of the object internally; which means the subject can manipulate (e. operate upon) that mental object with complete conservation of it.

Sensorimotor development concludes with the complete internalisation of the sensorimotor object. The type of object appropriate to the level of sensorimotor development is that upon which the subject can both sense and physically act upon, together. In contrast, there is a qualitatively higher set of objects which can either be sensed, or acted upon, but not both together. Examples of this set of objects includes colour (which can be sensed but not sucked, grasped, kicked or rattled), and simple ordinal counting (appropriate to action but not sensation). It takes a whole further qualitative stage of development to construct and internalise these latter types of objects: this stage is that of preoperational, or intuitive, intelligence.

The intuitive object is therefore qualitatively more advanced than the sensorimotor object, and of course subsumes it too. When it comes to understanding the nature of concrete operations, it is the precise nature of the intuitive object (which includes comprehending the limitations of the sensorimotor object) which must be grasped. Concrete operations operate upon the internalised intuitive object. When intuitive (preoperational) development completes, the subject is in possession of mental faculties whereby the concrete physical object gains an independence of its perceivable transformations through the ability to enact those transformations (and hence compensate for them) in thought.

It is in the descriptions of concrete operations where Piaget was most emphatic upon the property of reversibility. In helping us understand how the reversibility of operations is to be conceived, Chapman (1988) focused on the distinction between reversibility as such (mobile, internalised and immediate) with the relatively static attribute of revertibility. With a direct action that has not been internalised, one may indeed re-enact that action in the opposite direction, thus achieving revertibility of that action. But this is only to have "travelled" the relation circumscribed by that action in the two directions–it is not equivalent to having "seen" that action as an entity in itself. Only when the action is internalised does it become an immediately reversible operation. However, this terminology needs to be widened to comprehend the reversibility of all relations, as internalised transformations, and the restrictions implied by the notion of a physical action as such.

Without wanting to get into the task of deriving a full explanation of operations, it should nevertheless be apparent how this model of intelligence (at a certain qualitative level), where the object is internally produced (i.e. represented), no longer requires a description of thought only in terms of actions. For when the subject becomes powerful enough to represent the object, it also follows that the subject has internalised (or can at least mentally enact) all the relations and determinants of that object. Thus, it is not hard to foresee how the mental representation of the object will soon be followed by not so much the internalisation of mere actions upon the object, but of all transformations and relations of that object.

Concrete Operations

Now, the key to understanding the nature of concrete operations is to develop this model such that mental structures are seen to have been constructed which can than assimilate, directly, even passively, the inter- and intra- object relations that constitute transformations upon the object. Concrete operations where the reversibility is characterised by reciprocity are then easily understood as the internalised enactment of a transformation of a mental object. To judge one apple as "bigger than" another is mentally equivalent to performing the transformation of expanding the smaller apple to the size of the other, except that such a relation is only properly maintained in thought (i.e. conservable, with identity, permanence and compensations) when that relation is itself an object of thought–hence its immediate and instantaneous reversibility. What has happened is that the attribute of "bigger than" has been abstracted in itself, and becomes a schema in its own right: therefore, that schema assimilates (or produces) the relation independently to any actual and physical instance of that relation. For example, the representation of the colour yellow can only be representatively understood when it is also understood to be a "separate thing" to any particular object which happens to be yellow. If relations like bigger than" also become internalised in the same sense, then mental transformations within such relations can be understood precisely as transformations, and there is no need to try to reduce the relations to some notion of physical actions.

Concrete operations where the reversibility is characterised by negation are again understood as mental transformations of the objects mentally represented. In the paradigm of the two sets of coloured beads, the child is asked to compare the quantity of beads of one colour against the quantity of all the (wooden) beads, but the question is phrased in such a way as to force the actions of the positing and removing of the qualifying attributes of the beads as mental transformations.

It then becomes true to state that there are two sort of transformations that can be applied upon the concrete object. In the first place, the concrete object can be "placed" and "taken away", which amounts to the same thing as willfully assimilating the object to a particular schema (e.g. to permit a particular bead into the mobile schema of yellow beads), or denying that assimilation (e.g. to take a particular bead out of the set of yellow beads), which means that the transformation of this type is characterised by the reversibility of negation. And in the second place, the object in itself can be transformed: it can be made bigger or smaller, longer or shorter, thicker or thinner, brighter or duller, hotter or colder, lighter or heavier, etc. In contrast to classificatory operations, such relational transformations do not negate the object, but rather relate it to another object, both of which are being assimilated upon the same attribute. Note that the transformation of making the object longer, for example, is qualitatively the same as comparing two objects treated as identical except for their length: they are both being assimilated to the one attribute of length, but such that that attribute is conserved despite the fact it is being transformed.

Classificatory operations (reversed by negation) assimilate or reject the object according to the attribute. Relational operations (reversed by reciprocity) transform the object within the attribute. In respect to a single particular attribute (e.g. colour), classificatory operations determine how the object is the same as other objects, while relational operations determine how the object is different to other objects. [NB: Even the relation of symmetry (grouping VI) is to consider how the object may or may not be different to others in terms of the one attribute.] It is the fact that thought operates upon objects as such, and the manner in which such objects undergo transformations with respect to their abstracted attributes, that leads directly to the split between the two types of reversibility.

Number

At the level of concrete operations the issue of number and basic arithmetic gives rise to many paradoxes due to the manner in which Piaget presented his theory of operations. First and foremost, number itself is an operational construction and is not in itself sufficiently permanent, conserved or objective, unless also included in the basic operations of addition and subtraction. In other words, if one is to sensibly talk about number, a basic understanding of addition and subtraction necessarily goes hand-in-hand with it.

In Piaget’s description of number, the arithmetic operations are reversible actions, just as for the eight groupings of intensive logic, except that this time they form an algebraic group rather than a grouping. However, Piaget also described number as a synthesis, or fusing, of the intensive operations of classifications and relations. In particular, addition and subtraction might be seen as "reducible" to a synthesis of groupings I (primary addition of classes) and V (simple seriations). Herein lies the first paradox: how can number and arithmetic be described, on the one hand, as their own system of operations, as internalised and reversible actions of thought, and on the other hand, as a "synthesis" of other types of internalised action?

A second paradox arises from Piaget’s description for how classificatory and relational operations, at the concrete level, must remain separate systems (because classificatory and relational operations cannot be operationally combined with each other), and yet number is described as a "synthesis" of these two types of reversibility. If the two types of reversibility cannot be concretely "combined", what does it mean to talk of their "synthesis"?

I would argue that the above paradoxes arise, not because the theory is particularly wrong, but because of Piaget’s insistence of talking about operations as internalised actions. The terminology of operations, as such, is probably extremely apt for the logico-mathematical analysis and presentation which Piaget made (coming from the concerns epistemology), but is not so apt when the concern is primarily psychological. Seltman & Seltman (1985) published a work in which Piaget was criticised for conflating a logical analysis with a psychological one (among others), and came to the conclusion that Piaget’s entire theory must therefore be fundamentally flawed. However, I would contend that such a conclusion is premature and unhelpful, especially as Seltman & Seltman provided no evidence of comprehending the difficult problems which Piaget was tackling. Instead, I am contending that Piaget’s theory is fundamentally correct, and that the problem is to clarify the "conflations" and confusions of terminology, and to improve the theory, not to dispense with it.

Let us first justify Piaget’s claim that the two systems of concrete operations of classifications and relations cannot be combined within a single system (operationally) at the concrete level. The solution gains a little clarity if we use our model of the internalised, mental (and still concrete) object, produced in thought. The answer is that it is simply meaningless to both posit the object according to the attribute and transform (i.e. relate) the object within that attribute at the same time. Either the object is there or it isn’t (hence the classification); if it is not there then it can’t be transformed; and if it is there, then any attempt to transform it prohibits the possibility of removing it (i.e. at the same time as transforming it). One can perform the operation of including the class of red beads within the class of wooden beads (as a concrete and directly presented configuration), but then within the same concrete context, to start taking about each bead as being "more red" or "less wooden" than another (i.e., performing operations of reciprocity) simply has no bearing or meaning upon the classificatory operations, or vice versa. For this reason, the two types of reversibility — negation and reciprocity, as described above — cannot operationally combine among themselves in any concretely meaningful way.

Then, to explain the paradox where number appears as a "synthesis" of the "un-combineable" operations of classifications and relations, we have to understand the qualitative nature of the object which intelligence has abstracted and internalised at the point by which concrete operations become active. This, however, is a task of immense proportions, and which I have begun to take on, but which cannot be properly presented in this essay. Instead, the following notes will have to suffice. In the paradigms of the conservation of basic quantity (i.e. pouring a quantity of liquid from a tall, thin glass to a short, wide glass; and changing the shape and size of a ball of modeling clay), intuitive intelligence concludes by having abstracted all the perceivable attributes of the object (e.g. length, width, colour) from the object itself. Well, if all the perceivable attributes have gained an independence from the physical object, what is left to constitute the physical object in itself? The answer is some notion of basic "substance" and "quantity". These latter abstractions are what remain permanent in the face of perceived (but judged to be irrelevant!) transformations of the object.

If all perceivable transformations and attributes of the intuitive object have been abstracted (and become independent of) that object, then intelligence has developed to the level of having produced the concrete object. The concrete object becomes, for the first time, a true abstract concept, since it is no longer reducible to its sensible (and motor) components. But what this level of abstraction also means is that intelligence can now operate upon the object either according to transformations of its (represented) attributes (hence the eight groupings of intensive logic) or according to the concrete object in the absence of all such attributes–leading to number. As Piaget wrote, number involves the production of a unit which is both identical to (i.e. same as) and separate from (i.e. different to) any other unit. The concrete object can constitute such a unit thanks to the level of abstraction achieved.

In this context, the way to resolve the aforementioned paradox (without providing a comprehensive treatment here), is to consider the subject and its schemata as a unity (in the Kantian sense) which has all these different ways upon which it can manipulate and transform the concrete object. As a unity, the subject’s schemata produce number simultaneously with intensive logical operations, since the whole thing derives from the general qualitative nature of the abstractions made. There is then no need to "synthesise" classificatory operations with relational ones to produce number (since thought, as a unit, operates upon the same objects), and number can indeed engender its own operations without them having to be reducible in some way to intensive operations.

Conclusion

From the point of view of (late) intuitive and (early) concrete intelligence, an attribute of an object is a perceivable entity which has become an abstracted object of though in itself. As such, an attribute has, representatively, become "liberated" from any actual object bearing that attribute. Operations, then, are apparent in the sense that the subject is able to represent those attributes which, in fact, can only be objectified as perceived transformations of the object. For example, sensorimotor development cannot understand colour, despite being able to perceive it, because sensorimotor schemata are not sufficiently advanced as to be able to transform colour independently to the coloured object. Cognitive development throughout the preoperational (or intuitive) period serves precisely to abstract such attributes from the objects to which they pertain, ready for concrete operations to make use of in their own right.

However, if (some of) Piaget’s rather one-sided terminology is to be adhered to, a concrete operation would become an action that is enacted somewhere in the subject’s mind, and immediately reversed (as an identical action in the opposite direction), every time the particular relation in question has to be thought about. Clearly, this model is too mechanical and primitive, and Piaget himself insisted upon the simultaneous integration of any operation within an immediate and co-existent system of multiple operations. Instead, if one considers how the subject’s intelligence has internalised, objectified and abstracted those relations upon which operations are supposed to bear, then one has a model whereby thought becomes more akin to assimilation (though also production) and less laborious–at least for those relations already comprehended.

I would also contend this latter model is more intuitively acceptable to ourselves (as adults who constructed all these abstractions many years ago). For example, in the various conservation of quantity paradigms mentioned above, the fact that the quantity of water remains the same despite its transformations appears to us to be "obvious" and instantaneous; we do not feel the labour of having to perform mental actions.

References

Chapman, M (1988). Constructive Evolution: Origins and Development of Piaget’s Thought. Cambridge University Press.

Piaget, J (1965). The Child’s Conception of Number. Norton & Co.

Piaget, J (1983). The Origin of Intelligence in the Child. Penguin Books.

Piaget, J (1987). Possibility and Necessity: Volume 1. University of Minnesota Press.

Piaget, J (1987). Possibility and Necessity: The Role of Necessity in Cognitive Development. Volume 2. University of Minnesota Press.

Seltman, M. M. & Seltman, P. (1985). Piaget’s Logic: A Critique of Genetic Epistemology. Unwin Hyman.

Table of Contents


MINUTES OF THE ANNUAL BUSINESS MEETING

THE JEAN PIAGET SOCIETY:

SOCIETY FOR THE STUDY OF KNOWLEDGE AND DEVELOPMENT

Saturday, June 21, 1997

Santa Monica, CA

1. Minutes of the 1996 Annual Business Meeting. Cynthia Lightfoot, Secretary.

The Minutes from last year’s Business Meeting were approved.

2. Financial Report. William Gray, Treasurer.

Gray reported that the accounts show evidence of the Society’s continuing good health and progress towards financial stability.

3. Announcements. Michael Chandler, President.

Chandler extended appreciation to members of the Symposium Committee–Larry Nucci, Geoffrey Saxe, and Elliot Turiel–who organized our 1997 Symposium on Culture, Thought, and Development. He also complimented members of the Local Arrangements Committee–Patricia Greenfield, Connie Milbrath, and our new student member, Myrna Gwen–whose hard work was apparent at every level, and made possible a particularly smooth running event.

Retiring officers and Board members were thanked for their significant contributions to the Society. Although their term of office will expire in October, we are very fortunate that Terrance Brown (Past President), and Marvin Berkowitz, Patricia Miller, Gil Noam, and Elliot Turiel (Board members) have agreed to continue serving the Society in an ex-officio capacity.

4. Nominations for the Board of Directors.

The slate of Board candidates to serve the 1997-2000 term (Edith Ackermann, Rolando Garcia, Orlando Lourenço, Sue Taylor Parker, and Judith Smetana) was proposed and approved unanimously.

5. Local Arrangements Report. Patricia Greenfield, Chair, Local Arrangements Committee.

Greenfield reported that approximately 20 students from area high schools, colleges, and universities lended time and effort to a variety of tasks including registering conference attendees, directing traffic through the hotel, assisting with audiovisual and lighting equipment, and chauffeuring plenary and invited speakers and board members. All were thanked for their contributions, especially Paula Averson and Myrna Gwen.

6. New Business.

We were encouraged to call to the Board’s attention any issues or concerns which may prove relevant to future business, and to provide feedback regarding the 1997 Symposium. Killen made note of the exceptional volunteer force and its role in the overall success of the Symposium. She suggested that it be a model for future symposia.

Table of Contents


TWENTY-SEVENTH SPRING MEETING OF THE BOARD OF DIRECTORS THE JEAN PIAGET SOCIETY: SOCIETY FOR THE STUDY OF KNOWLEDGE AND DEVELOPMENT

Wednesday, June 18, 1997
Holiday Inn - Bayview Plaza
Santa Monica, CA

Present: Eric Amsel, Marvin Berkowitz, Tom Bidell, Terrance Brown, James Byrnes, Michael Chandler (presiding),Theo Dawson, William Gray, Patricia Greenfield, Myrna Gwen, Melanie Killen, Chris Lalonde, Cynthia Lightfoot (recording), Orlando Lourenço, Connie Milbrath, David Moshman, Gil Noam, Larry Nucci, Geoffrey Saxe, Ellin Scholnick, Anastasia Tryphon, Elliot Turiel, Cecilia Wainryb.

I. WELCOME TO NEW BOARD MEMBERS

A. Cecilia Wainryb was welcomed as a newly elected member of the 1997-99 Board.

B. We are fortunate also to be able to add to our ranks the following individuals whose terms of office run 1997-2000:

Edith Ackerman Rolando Garcia
Orlando Lourenço Sue Taylor Parker
Judith Smetana

C. New and continuing ex-officio members of the Board include:

Eric Amsel (Membership) Trevor Bond (Outreach)
Theo Dawson (Publications) Rheta DeVries (Outreach)
Wolfgang Edelstein (Nominations) Chris Lalonde (Publications)
Jonas Langer (Nominations) John Meacham (Membership)
Connie Milbrath (Symposium)

D. Myrna Gwen, who made significant contributions to the local arrangements of this year’s Symposium, was welcomed as our new Student Member.

II. OLD BUSINESS

A. The minutes of the Oct. 12, 1996 meeting were approved as recorded.

III. NEW BUSINESS

A. President’s Remarks (Chandler)

i. Resignations. Dante Cicchetti was obliged to resign his position on the Board, but hoped that he might in the future be able to lend a hand to the Society.

ii. Absent Colleagues. It was decided at the Winter Executive Committee Meeting that we would mark the occasion of the death of our colleague Ed Reed, as well as those of Mimi Sinclair and Barbel Inhelder, by dedicating the 1997 Symposium to the three of them. In addition, special memorial symposia for Sinclair and Inhelder have been scheduled into the 1997 program, and similar events will be made available to honor Reed at the 1998 Symposium. Their passing will also be acknowledged in the Genetic Epistemologist, forthcoming issues of which will include out-takes of their works.

iii. Decisions taken on suspect authority.

a. The GE. Chris Lalonde, who has served on the Publications Committee, overseen our list server, and developed and maintained our Website, has generously agreed to take on yet another task of major importance and urgency as Guest Editor for the Genetic Epistemologist. Lalonde had on hand a copy of a forthcoming issue, scheduled soon for publication.

b. Registration fee waivers. It was decided at the Winter Executive Committee Meeting that 1997 conference registration fees would be waived for all plenary and invited speakers.

iv. Various gift horses.

a. Updating the Blue Book. Special thanks are due to members of the Symposium Committee who have revised, extended and updated the Symposium Manual in the Blue Book.

b. Retiring Board Members. Prompted by Brown’s attempt to sneak out the door before the bell rings, Chandler reminded us that Board Members whose terms of office expire in 1997 remain on duty until the Fall meeting of the Board, at which time newly elected members are formally installed into their offices. Marvin Berkowitz, Terrance Brown, and Elliot Turiel, who will rotate off the Board in October, were thanked for their invaluable service to the Society.

v. A preview of problems to come.

a. Symposia 1998, 1999. In order to make a more workable plan, Bearison and Selman have withdrawn their proposal for a 1998 symposium on theory and practice. If it were to proceed in 1999, the symposium would then coincide with Harvard’s 50th anniversary–a situation which might be used to our advantage. Chandler noted that perhaps Brown, Bidell, and Garcia’s proposal, originally intended for 1999, could be moved ahead in order to fill the lacuna.

b. The GE. Dealing with the loss of Ed Reed’s capable stewardship of the GE remains a priority. Although Chris Lalonde has stepped forward as a particularly well suited Guest Editor, at the time of this meeting we do not have an individual elected to the position to carry on future work.

c. LEA. We need to appraise our increasingly complex relationship with Lawrence Erlbaum, which now includes the possibility of sponsoring the production of a journal.

d. Papers & Posters. Debated at both the Winter Executive Committee Meeting and on e-mail, the relative merits of requesting that paper submissions be converted into posters require evaluation.

e. Membership. Membership is a perennial problem. Adding 100-200 to our roster would create a fiscal zone of comfort within which we could consider alternatives to our current hand-to-mouth lifestyle -- providing travel grants to international symposium participants, for example.

IV. THE VICE PRESIDENT’S REPORT (Byrnes)

A. 1997 Symposium submissions. James Byrnes distributed a detailed summary of submissions for the 1997 Symposium. Proposal submissions were 20% higher than expected. There was a total of 111 presentations scheduled, 45 of which originated from countries outside North America. There was discussion of the acceptance rate (94%), which was higher than usual, and the degree to which it is or ought to be hooked to the volume of poster presentations. International submissions were also discussed, including the possibility of allowing for submissions in French and Spanish. It was noted at this point that presenters from outside North America often need financial assistance in order to attend the meetings.

B. Preparation and publication of the program. There was some discussion regarding the need to work out a method by which appropriate members of the Board are charged with overseeing and proof reading the Program. The intention is to eliminate ambiguity as to when the program production manager is to instruct the printer to run the final copy.

V. STANDING COMMITTEE REPORTS

A. Finance Committee Report (Gray, Moshman)

i. Current figures. Gray noted that we are currently 380 members strong, and that our pre-registration figure of 141 includes invited and plenary speakers. History suggests that we can expect 80 more registrants. The following figures reflect our worth, in dollar amount, over the past few years, and show increasing financial good health:

1993: $11,616.49
1994: 22,777.63
1995: 41,511.91
1996: 41,608.50

ii. Membership goals. Gray cautioned against a collective complacency in light of our excellent current financial condition (approximately 60k in the bank, although we have not yet paid out our major expenses - Symposium, GE, 1997 volume, board travel). He reminded us of our membership needs of a minimum of 450 in order to meet our contractual obligations to LEA.

iii. An annual budget. It was reported that a process has been initiated through which a proposed annual budget will be presented to the Board each October. The first such presentation is planned for October, 1997.

iv. Miscellany. Brown inquired about the possibility of making financial investments. Chandler asked that this be considered by the Finance Committee in the context of its long range planning. He also asked that the Finance Committee create a figure to serve as a spending guide for the Symposium Committee. Killen suggested that we make it common practice to waive the registration fees for invited speakers. The topic will be placed on the agenda for the October meeting of the Board.

B. Membership Committee Report (Berkowitz)

i. Non-renewing members. Berkowitz reported on the success of the letter writing campaign urging individuals whose membership status is lapsing to renew. As outgoing Chair who will continue to assist the Committee in an ex-officio capacity, he has offered to help Goldin-Meadow (incoming Chair) institute the procedure.

ii. New members. Berkowitz asked for a reasoned figure to use as a goal in recruiting new members. Brown reported that he and others had considered it some years ago and concluded that 600 members would provide a comfortable level of financial security. He noted further that this figure may have been outdated by changes in the fee structure and Gray’s especially competent management of the treasury.

iii. Members’ brochure. The brochure has been updated, printed, and distributed with Theo Dawson’s expert and greatly appreciated assistance. Berkowitz distributed copies to those of us in attendance, suggesting that we include them in our correspondence and make an orchestrated effort to have them available at professional meetings. Brown commented on their potential utility to Local Arrangements in publicizing the Society.

iv. Swapping lists. Berkowitz coordinated an opportunity to exchange mailing lists with AME. Brown motioned that we do so; Killen seconded. The motion was approved unanimously.

v. Miscellany. Chandler asked the Committee to be attentive to the possibility of our membership becoming increasingly fluid as our Symposia venue becomes more mobile. Scholnick cautioned that we may be obliged to pay more per volume when Symposia topics are not sufficiently marketable. On the same topic, Amsel made note of the possible tension between what sells books and what is intellectually exciting. There was a discussion regarding consequences to our membership of changes in our relationship with LEA. In reference to our desire to encourage the attendance of international scholars, it was pointed out that ISSBD uses some of its considerable conference fee (more than double our own) to support the travel of participants from the third world. This matter was referred back to the committee.

C. Outreach Committee Report (Noam)

i. Supporting international scholars. Noam pointed to the international representation at this years Symposium as hard evidence of the success of recent outreach efforts. Thus far, efforts have taken primarily an intellectual form, i.e., opportunities have been provided for international scholars to present their work. Noam asked that more consideration be given to how we might provide financial assistance to those in need of it. Chandler concurred, and pushed for concrete action on the matter. He called for a straw vote to commit $2000 per year to support the attendance at JPS of financially needy international scholars. Noam suggested that the Outreach Committee be charged with evaluating requests and decisions on disbursing the funds. Brown warned against expending limited resources, and suggested that the Outreach Committee look into the possibility of securing external funds. Chandler asked for the drafting of a more detailed proposal, perhaps in time for the October meeting. He noted as well that waiving registration fees for our international colleagues would not impose too much of a financial burden on the Society.

ii. Showcasing practice. Noam suggested that a symposium or other scholarly event focused on the topic of practice be made a regular feature of our annual Symposia.

iii. Miscellany. It was noted that Rheta DeVries stepped forward this past year and agreed to be the keynote speaker at the annual meeting of the ACT held in St. Louis. Noam asked that we forward to him or other committee members names and contact information of international individuals who might be interested in the Society. He will continue to serve the Outreach Committee in an ex-officio capacity. Chandler announced that Killen is to be co-chair of the Outreach committee.

** Chandler welcomed Judy Amsel who agreed to join us and act as a resource
person as we deliberate on our current and future dealings with LEA**

D. Publications Committee Report (Killen/Scholnick)

i. Royalties on the Symposium Series. Scholnick circulated a table detailing the number of copies sold and royalties received from each book in our Symposium Series. With special reference to our two most recent volumes, she noted that the net income to LEA appears generous and provides a positive measure of the mutually beneficial relationship which the Society shares with its publisher.

ii. The GE. In addition to contending with the personal loss surrounding Ed Reeds death, we are confronted with a host of practical problems regarding the production of the GE. Chris Lalonde was thanked yet again for stepping forward as Guest Editor. Acting on the recommendation of the Publications Committee, it was moved that he formally assume the position of Editor of the GE, with the Publications Committee acting as an advisory group. The motion was seconded and approved unanimously. Questions were raised about the future of the GE; in particular, whether it is necessary or desirable to produce a hard copy in addition to electronic version which is currently available at our website. Scholnick motioned that we undertake a year-long experiment in which the GE is made available in both media–print and electronic–and that readers be polled regarding their preferences for one or the other, or both. Byrnes seconded. The motion carried.

iii. Dealings with LEA. It was noted that LEA appears to be moving towards more profit-conscious practices which could impact the Society in several ways. Among the more positive consequences is the possibility of their willingness to forge a partnership with JPS to establish a Society sponsored journal. The mutual gains of such a partnership include additional subscribers (e.g., adding the journal to our current package of Membership benefits, or providing members with a reduction in subscription price), and publicity for the Society. Questions were raised about the risks entailed in an enterprise of this nature. Amsel explained that in general risks depend on the particular details of the partnership. For example, financial risk is eliminated if a society’s responsibilities are largely editorial; alternatively, profit-sharing is possible in the case of ownership or joint-ownership. Chandler will organize an ad hoc committee including representatives from the Publications, Finance, and Membership Committees to explore these possibilities.

TWENTY-SEVENTH SPRING MEETING OF THE BOARD OF DIRECTORS THE JEAN PIAGET SOCIETY: SOCIETY FOR THE STUDY OF KNOWLEDGE AND DEVELOPMENT

Saturday, June 21, 1997
Holiday Inn - Bayview Plaza
Santa Monica, CA

Present: Edith Ackerman, Eric Amsel, Marvin Berkowitz, Tom Bidell, Terrance Brown, Michael Chandler (presiding), Rheta DeVries, Rolando Garcia, William Gray, Patricia Greenfield, Chris Lalonde, Connie Milbrath, David Moshman, Gil Noam, Larry Nucci, Sue Parker, Geoffrey Saxe, Elliot Turiel, Cecilia Wainryb.

I. ANNOUNCEMENTS.

Rheta DeVries reported on a project which would bring Mimi Sinclair’s biography up to date, and perhaps make Piaget’s work more widely accessible. Sinclair’s husband has donated some funds towards producing a bibliography and compilation of unpublished works, all of which might be most appropriately overseen by the Society. There was a discussion regarding the form (e.g., book, pamphlet) and distribution (e.g., Website) of the final product. Chandler suggested that the Society give serious consideration to sponsoring the project, and asked for a more detailed proposal to consider at the October meeting.

II. STANDING COMMITTEE REPORTS (cont.).

A. Nominations Committee Report (Brown)

i. Standing committee assignments. Brown circulated for consideration a list of proposed committee assignments. Byrnes asked that his name be removed from the Membership Committee on account of his service obligation to Publications. Pointing to the uncertainty surrounding the 1997 symposium, Chandler recommended that the final composition of the committee be decided once the 1998 and 1999 program organizers have been identified. Brown motioned for accepting the committee assignments as revised. Moshman seconded; the motion carried.

B. Symposium Committee Report (Turiel)

i. Turiel reported on the Committee’s activities associated with organizing the 1997 symposium, and making plans for 1998.

ii. The other major undertaking of the Committee has been the revision of the Symposium Manual, a draft of which was circulated. It is intended as a working document, and feedback was requested. Based on her experiences organizing this year’s local arrangements, Greenfield will add to the Manual. Saxe requested that more information be made available regarding the timing and sequencing of events. He noted that Dawson, in particular, could be assisted with better developed guidelines. Gray provided data concerning expenditures in the various categories. Chandler thanked all who have contributed thus far.

III. PROPOSALS FOR 1998, 1999, AND BEYOND

A. The 1998/1999 problem. Chandler opened for discussion how to best cope with Bearison and Selman’s retraction of their proposal for a 1998 symposium on theory and practice. The proposal has been on the table for quite some time, and discussed in detail and with approval at several previous meetings of the Board. An updated version of the proposal was circulated. Chandler suggested that it be held for consideration for 1999 or some later date, and that we proceed to encourage Brown, Bidell, and Garcia to push ahead by one year their proposed symposium on reductionism, which is the most fully developed alternative proposal currently in hand. In this context Jim Byrnes announced that in the course of giving thought to our dilemma he had approached Goldin-Meadow and others on the possibility of a 1998 Symposium organized around the theme of Language and Learning, or perhaps, Language, Literacy, and Learning. In addition to the inherent appeal of the subject, and the ways in which it could be made to include issues relevant to practitioners and teachers, a principal advantage is that we can quickly assemble a list of potential invited speakers and plenaries. Coupling the topic with a familiar venue–Chicago, for instance–would make for a workable plan under exceptional circumstances. Concern was expressed regarding the feasibility of fleshing out the idea in the scant amount of time available. Discussion turned to the proposal for a Symposium on reductionism. Interest in international outreach and the prospect of Garcia’s organizational involvement combined for many to make Mexico City an attractive venue. Possible speakers and a general format were discussed, as well as how to extend the debate beyond biology and neuropsychology to include studies of culture. Despite the enthusiasm of others for moving the proposal into the 1998 slot, Brown held that the proposal is far less mature than he would like, and reiterated his preference for 1999. There was a straw vote regarding the 1998 Symposium: 11 favored Reductionism in Mexico City; 5 favored Language in Chicago. Although generally enthusiastic about helping to organize a JPS symposium in Mexico City, Garcia expressed additional and strongly held reservations about whether one could be prepared for 1998 under the cloud of current, short-term political instabilities. There was a second vote in light of these reservations. Jim Byrnes’ offer to organize on very short notice a 1998 Symposium on language was accepted–we will meet in Chicago next June. Brown, Bidell and Garcia are to organize a 1999 Symposium on reductionism to convene in Mexico City.

IV. OTHER BUSINESS

The Fall Board meeting will take place in Chicago, October 4, 1997.

Table of Contents


Editor’s Note

by Chris Lalonde

The sudden death of Edward Reed–the former editor of the Genetic Epistemologist–in February of this year created both personal anguish for those who knew him, and a certain inevitable chaos in the production of this publication. As a result, you will have noticed that recent issues of the GE have been arriving both late and out of sequence. I hope that you will bear with me as I try (with the help of Theo Dawson and members of the JPS Publications Committee) to catch up on back issues and work toward re-establishing our regular publication schedule. Two more issues, meant to round out the four issues of 1997, will follow rather quickly on the heels of this one and will include brief excerpts from the writings of Edward Reed and Hermina Sinclair.


© 1995-1998 The Jean Piaget Society

Send comments to: webmaster@piaget.org

Last update: 19 September 1998